Limits on prediction markets?

If a prediction market is not liquid enough, it’s possible to manipulate it by throwing in small sums of money (thus, for example, a political candidate could boost his price by buying a bunch of shares). Presumably this could be useful, for example if you pump up your market share price, this might induce donors to contribute to the winning cause or could help attract endorsements. Of course, not every company needs to do this and stock like the air nz stock often carries itself but every so often, a business may make a wrong decision resulting in a stock drop and they need to pick it back up.

At the other extreme, if the market is too liquid, there’s a potential “moral hazard” or motivation to throw an election, to purposely hurt your side in order to make money on the pointspread if you’ve already placed a large bet in the other direction.

Now here’s my question: there’s clearly a sense in which a prediction market can be too small (too illiquid) to be trusted, and conversely if it is too large (too liquid) you get problems in the other direction. Is there an intermediate zone in which the market is liquid enough so it can’t be easily manipulated, but not so liquid that it motivates point-shaving? Or do the zones of “too illiquid” and “too liquid” actually overlap, so there’s no market size that does the job?

I imagine the answer would depend on some external parameters, such as the ease or difficulty of enforcing insider-trading restrictions. Possibly there’s some theoretical work in this area. Justin? Robin?

P.S. I’m raising the questions above in all sincerity. This post is not intended to be a devastating argument that shoots down prediction markets; I’d just like to know if these issues have been considered and resolved in some way. A lot of the casual discussions of prediction markets have been of the “they’re cool” or “they’re silly” variety, but I imagine the researchers in this area have considered ways of assessing the problems arising from the issues noted above.

P.P.S. This paper by Robin Hanson (see comment below) discusses the first of these points, presenting theory and evidence that low-volume markets are hard to manipulate and thus implying that there is an intermediate zone where the markets can work well.

4 thoughts on “Limits on prediction markets?

  1. Andrew,
    Ironically, Paul Tetlock from UTexas found exactly the opposite. He found that very liquid markets on TradeSports had some big price anomalies (overpricing low probability events and underpricing high probability events), while less liquid markets were much more efficient. This is from his conclusion:
    "A leading explanation is that illiquid markets have fewer noise traders, and periods of illiquidity prevent arbitrageurs from profiting on short-term trades that would destabilize prices.
    Additional statistical tests provide support for the idea that liquidity serves as a proxy for non-informational or noise trading. The key finding is that the prices of illiquid securities converge toward terminal cash flows much more rapidly than the prices of liquid securities. This implies that non-informational or noise trading is prevalent during periods of liquidity, which may help explain the observed mispricing in liquid securities."

  2. If moral hazards are a problem, they could be substantially reduced by having the exchanges make the identity of people involved in each trade public.

    Traders and businesses trying to make money serving those traders won't like such a rule, but people who want to subsidize prediction markets to create informative prices might create such markets. It won't be easy to collect enough evidence to determine whether this strategy is desirable.

  3. if price fails to reflect information, then arbitrage is possible. If a price fails to attract the attention of even the speculators and other informed party,then, how could it be of any use as a PR tool ?

Comments are closed.